01/11/2024 - 01/30/24
Zihan
We have learned about the individual optimization and profit maximazition. In these problems, we typically take some elements as given. For example, in UMP, the prices are given. So, in these cases, we are actually looking for partial equilibrium.
Now, under a simple model, we work on a general equilibrium,
We have at least two goods.
For simplicity, we consider a static enviornment, in which transactions will not be repeated.
Agents: (individuals or households), indexed by
Goods: We have
Agents are characterized by
their consumption sets:
their preferences over consumption bundles in
Preferences are represented by utility functions, namely
Utility functions need the utility function to be continuous, increasing, and semi quasi concave. (This one is Assumption 1
)
Their endowments:
We assume agents have competitive behavior, they take prices as given. (This means each one agent cannot change the price by himself, but this does not mean the price is exogeneously given).
We also assume agents are able to buy and sell any quantities of good they want, which means no friction
Definition 1. Allocation:
Allocation is a list
We need the allocation to be feasible, which means it cannot exceed the aggregate number of endowments, i.e.
The leading example:
Definition 2. Pareto optimum.
A feasible allocation
Explanation to this defination:
For a feasible allocation
It is Pareto efficient if there exists no other allocation
such that for all consumers , with at least one preference relation strict . The process that an allocation
moves to such that for all consumers , with at least one preference relation strict is called Pareto improvement. In other word, an allocation is Pareto efficient if there is no Pareto improvement.
Graphical presentation: Contract curve
All Pareto efficient allocation in Edgeworth box.
Special cases: prefect substitutes; perfect complements
For smooth IC curves, PO allocation one points of tangetly btw IC curves
Problems with PO allocation,
we cannot rank them
we cannot always even rank PO allocation versus non PO allocations
An allocation where one agent gets all the resources is a PO.
Definition3. Competitive
An allocation
Given
market clearing conditions
An example
Definition: Compatitive equilibrium /Walrasian equilibrium
A competitive (Walrasian) equilibrium is a pair
Then we have several famous theorems
[First welfare theorem]: Every competitive allocation is a Pareto Optimum (PO)
[Second welfare theorem]: Any PO allocation can be supported (reached) by with some dedistribution of resources.
Another example
Suppose the utilitty for two consumers are
Endowments:
, How do we derive the competitive equilibrium?
Given
, individual 1 solves By solving this UMP problem,
We can solve the same UMP problem for individual 2 as well,
Then, applying the market clearing condition, what we obtained is,
and,
Two equations above give the same result of price ratio.
subsitute this result back to the demand function, we can get the number of demand for each individual under this endowment.
Here in this example, we did something redundant. Actually we just need one market to be clear, and the other one will be automatically clear as well.
Given endowment
Definition. Feasible allocation and "block"
Let
Under an another allocation, it could be slightly better, i.e.
如果一个allocation
但是即使是Pareto optimum,它这个allocation 仍然可以被其中一个人block。(block by one individual)
Definition. Core
The core of an exchange economy with endowment
推论:Show that
, explain it in own words. Everyone in the "core" is a pareto optimum Suppose there exists a feasible allocation
such that but . Therefore, by definition of Pareto Optimum, there exists a feasible allocation
such that , but some , which has the same meaning of , and for some , . Hence, we know that , which is contradictory to . Hence, whenever
, , which implies .
Recall that we assume agent's utility function satisfies continuity, semi quasi concavity and increasing (strictly increasing), (This is assumption 1
).
Each individual is price taker. Given
when
Existance of
Individual
Aggregate excess demand for good
Theorem - Walras law
Let Assumption 1
, then
This actually means that the value of aggregate excess demand will always be zero at any set of positive prices.
Proof
By
Assumption 1
, It implies budget constraint holds with equality for all, Then,
Thus, if we aggregate over all the individuals it becomes, (note that the order of summation is not important)
Then we obtained what we wanna prove:
An immediate implication of the walres law is that the following:
If given some set of prices that are strictly positive, if
Definition - Walrasian equilibrium
A vector of prices
Walrasian equilibrium 定义的是价格。它使所有商品都不存在超额需求/供给
In this definition, we define equilibrium as price vector. However, the allocation
Theorem - Existance of Walrasian equilibrium,
If each individual's utility function satisfies Assumption 1
, and
Definition. [Walrasian allocation] - Given Walrasian equilibrium price
is the Walrasian equilibrium allocation.
From this, we have two observations
.
Observation 1
let
Proof
For homework!
Suppose
is a Walrasian equilibrium, and is the corresponding Walrasian allocation. and is not feasible. So we have , which means that , which violates the definition of Walrasian allocation that . Contradiction! So any Walrasian equilibrium must be an feasible allocation.
Observation 2
if
This looks quite similar to WARA, if there is some better off utility allocation, it cannot be affordable.
if
Proof
For homework.
We wanna show hat if
, then , Suppose there exists some new allocation such that
, but , therefore, let , where are some small numbers, then there could be some such that and because is assumed to be strictly increasing. Therefore, it contradicts with the statement of if , then .
Let
Theorem
Let
This implies that every WE alllcation is in the core.
Proof
Proof by contradiction,
On the contrary, there exist
such that and , Since
is Waralsian equailibrium allocation, then from the oberservation 1
,, it is a feasible allocation. Then there exists an alternative allocation
and a subset of individuals , such that blocks with . That is
, for all , and for some . We can multiply both sides of
with , then it becomes . And from
Observation 2
,for all , and for some , we sum up all individuals in ,
, there is a contradiction.
Definition
Let
Suppose
Note that here each
This allocation
The lagrange function should be like,
FOCs for interior solution give (Here
Example
Two individuals
Say the endowment:
And the utility function
For Agent
, Then,
FOCs:
,
,
This implies,
Substitute with some budget constraints,
, which gives us
describing the PEA.
In Walrasian equilibrium, each individual wants to choose a bundle that maximizes their own utility, She knows nothing about other individuals. By showing WEA is in the core, we have shown that it is possible to believe outcomes in the core without a central planner, which means the market works. that is because
Theorem - First Welfare theorem
If each individual's utility is strictly increasing that every WEA is pareto equilibrium.
Question: Can we consider a WEA as equitable or socially optimal?
It is clear that if an allocation is not pareto efficient, than not socially optimal.
Theorem - Second Welfare theorem
Let assumption 1
for all individuals, let
Proof
Since
is PE, , Since
satisfies Assumption 1
, then for all, and , the existence of WEA for and is guaranteed. Let ( )be WEA for economy and , Since under WEA each individual maximizes utilitty given initial endowment, we have,
Since
, we have Since
is PEA, cannot Pareto dominate (That means no such that ), Then
, Suppose
for some , if
then some is strictly increasing, then , contradict! Then
and , Then for
and , for some , (For simplicity let be the only individuals and ), Then by strict quasi concavity, by averaging bundles
and , i can have a new bundle , which gives a higher utility which is a contradiction.
A short summary for welfare theorems
Walrasian equilibrium allocation (WEA)
First welfare theorem: Walrasian Equilibrium
Pareto efficiency
No distortion of price
No externalities
No asymmetric information
No market power
Second welfare theorem:
Any Pareto efficient allocation can result from a Walrasian equilibrium (given that endowments can be redistributed in a lump sum way)
Example
let
Show Edgeworth box, find out PEA, find out WEA, and the prices
This economy in edgeworth box is
For the WEAs, we have to solve the UMP given endowments.
Homework
change the
and , show PEA in this economy
First derive the WEA,
For agent
Then,
The first order conditions are:
Then
, which implies, For agent B, he maximizes
Since the utility function is linear, we have to discuss by case.
If
, then , and In this case, by the market clearing condition,
, we derive , which does not make sense. If
, then , and , In this case, by the market clearing condition,
, . So it could be the WEA. If
, then , but we have under this price, so it could not be a feasible allocation under this price In summary, the WEA is
. Then, the PEA
The Green curve represents the PEA in the edgeworth box. All these POs lie on the edge of the box.
We have production in the economy, but let's first consider the most simpliest Rubison economy
There is a firm producing coconut, selling it to Rubison and make profits. Rubison sells labor to the firm.
Say the production function is,
Say Rubinson's utility is,
, where
Rubinson has
Then the budget constraints for Robinson are,
Then, we can set the largrange by,
Here we know that actuall
So
The first-order conditions are,
Then we know the last constraint must be binding, and the solve for the first order conditions, l
Then combine with the budget constraint, we can derive the Rubinson's marshalian demand for coconut and labor,
(Here
Next lets consider the producer's problem. (profit max problem)
Then solve this problem, it gives us firm's demand on labor
And we can derive the profit as well
For completely solving the market equilibrium (general equilibrium), we need to consider the market clearing condition after deriving the partial equilibrium of these two markets.
Labor market clearing: labor demand = labor supply (leisure + labor. = T)
, which gives us
Exams on Feb. 8, TA sessions on Friday.